John Stuart Mill’s Harm Principle and the Right to Free Speech
Is there a Right to Free Speech: A measurement of Harm.
Speech is a means to communication, a free-flowing highway of information and gossip, but like a roadblock for traffic, interference from the state could be seen as inconvenient, or an unjustifiable limitation. Free speech, as defined by the Universal Declaration of Human Rights, is “Everyone has the right to freedom of opinion and expression; this right includes freedom to hold opinions without interference and to seek, receive and impart information and ideas through any media and regardless of frontiers.” (Warbuton,2). The right to free speech protects a person’s ability to express their opinions and views, no matter how controversial or fallible they are, without unjustified interference from the state. Although the right to free speech is rudimentary to basic human rights, there are factors that would justify government interference, censorship and regulation. These justifications include Mill’s harm principle, legal moralism, and the harm test.
Get Help With Your Essay
If you need assistance with writing your essay, our professional essay writing service is here to help!
Essay Writing Service
John Stuart Mill, describes the Harm Principle as, “The justification for interference with someone’s freedom to live their life as they choose is if they risk harming other people.” (Warbuton,23), indicating that your right to freedom of expression will be upheld until you clearly incite violence and or physical harm onto another. Although the harm principle is a pillar aspect to justifying the interference from the state, John Stuart Mill acknowledged the vulnerability of speech. He attributed speech as a way to obtain individual liberty while maintaining the majority interest, he quotes, “By saying what we think and by attending to the opinions and reactions of others, we as a society, are more likely to form better-justified and hence true beliefs.” (McGowan,771). It is evident that free speech is necessary for personal and communal growth, and this idea is expressed by two other theorists, Alexander Meiklejohn, and Thomas Scanlon. Meiklejohn takes the protection of speech from individual liberty to a vital aspect for democracy in his quote “A society will only be genuinely democratic if we are free to criticize the government, tell our representatives what we want them to do and freely discuss matters of public concern” (McGowan, 770). John S. Mill argues the importance of individual growth, while Alexander Meiklejohn advocates for the projected better function of a democratic society with the protection of free speech. In compression, Thomas Scanlon brings the two theories into question by advocating for individual liberty and autonomy, and claims that “If the state limits expression, then we are prevented from even considering some possibilities when deciding what to do and think.” (McGowan, 770). He points out the dangers of allowing state regulation and how it could impair our natural ability to obtain individual liberty. While it is evident that state-imposed limitation on one’s freedom of expression is parted on benefits over costs, there are some forms of expression that are unjustifiably harmful to the public health. With this in mind, all and any state intervention must be justified through the harm test.
The harm test measures and assesses the amount
and force of regulation that the state can impose on ones right to expression,
through three conditions: efficacy, minimal impairment, and proportionality,
(Sumner, 150). To justify paternalism by the state, the act of interference
must have expected success with no less intrusive policy applicable where the
benefits outweigh the costs (Sumner, 150). The harm test ensures that one’s
right to free speech is maintained to the highest level when state regulation
is deemed necessary. The way of which regulation can be deemed necessary is
through the theory of law known as legal moralism. Legal moralism is the view that the law can legitimately be used to
prohibit behaviors that conflict with society’s collective moral judgments even
when those behaviors do not result in physical or psychological harm to others
(Himma). An incident explored in the acclaimed article by The Atlantic, The Coddling of the American Mind,
addresses the importance of these three theories and the connection to legal
moralism. Trigger warnings have been utilized on campus as a form of protection
against potentially harmful content. These warnings are intended to provide
those who have trauma, to be prepared for conflict or harm. When applying the harm
principle, an unpopular or offensive message has little to do with physical
harm but rather psychological discomfort. In this regard, the harm principle
would be deemed irrelevant, and the pathway that would need to be taken to get
state interference would be through legal moralism. Common interest and morality are what deems
one’s actions to be immoral or intensely unpopular, and when conflicting with
the majority morality, regulation has the possibility to mimic the no platform
argument. When putting a filter on the opinions expressed by those who conflict
with others, there is a risk for developing a coping mechanism of “vindictive protectiveness”
(Lukainoff). This can ultimately end with inequality among those who’s
fundamental rights to expression are being infringed.
This
is where corporations and staff struggle to find a policy that reduces the
amount of harm caused by the sending of a message from a speaker to an audience
that is uninterested and reciprocal. When a speaker’s interest fails to fall in
unison with an audience, miscommunication can cause more harm than the actual
message being sent. A speaker expresses their opinions and ideas to engage in
communication and to be recognized as an informed citizen on public concern. An
audience member however, acknowledges the benefits of being the recipient of
other speeches, and can attend social gathers or seek out certain speakers to
become better informed, and facilitated in the pursuit of one’s ideas and
values. When a conflict of interest arises, it can create and endorse “a
constant state of outrage, even toward well-meaning speakers trying to engage
in genuine discussion” (Hadit). Limiting the opportunity for a speaker to send
certain messages can cause more issues then projected benefits. Harm, perhaps
rather than by the messages themselves, is being caused by the over censorship
of the offensive or unpopular messages. The
harm test, in contrast to Mills harm principle, addresses the danger of
inequality that comes with this regulation. He comments that “any restrictive
policy passes a harm test: the
government must be able to show that hate speech poses a significant risk of
harm to minorities that are its targets” (Sumner, 149). When applying this
quote by Mill to trigger warnings being used on campus the state has little
right to deny access to people’s rights to expression due to controversy and
offence, Sumner concludes that “forms of expression which pose no risk to
others then the freedom to engage in them must be inviolable” (149). Offensive
content or unpopular opinions can be destructive, annoying and indecent but are
not harmful. Offensive speech is vastly different than hate speech. If public
health and liberty are at risk due to immoral actions opinions and views, then
State regulation would be deemed appropriate. But since all citizens have the
fundamental right to free speech it would be immoral in itself to assume all
offensive and unpopular opinions are fallible. For the state to impose on one’s
freedom of expression to meet the demand for better public health and
individual liberty it would need to pass the harm test.
Hate
speech, in contrast to offensive or unpopular speech, is a given but complex
example of speech that has a high possibility of inciting violence and/or
physical harm onto another but is incredibly difficult to regulate. Hate
speech, “is a form of expression or communication, not itself violent, which
insults or defames a social group” (Sumner,142). For hate speech to be harmful,
the message sent to an individual or group must be targeting uncontrollable
aspects of their identity, things such as race, ethnicity, sexuality,
disability, and so on. Hate speech, although a form of an expression, is not
protected. An expression is the attempt to convey a meaning through the sending
of a message in any form and is protected by the Charter of rights and freedoms
(Sumner, 147). Fighting words are also not protected under section 2(b) of the
Charter of Freedoms and Rights. Fighting words are “those in the very utterance
inflict injury or tend to incite an immediate breach of peace” (Sumner, 147). Any
state-imposed legislation that is aimed to eliminate or punish hate speech
would be limiting some forms of expression and therefore infringing on section 2(b)
but is then saved under section One. Proving that although one has the right to
free speech, it is not unconditional nor is it free from criminalization.
To
further show how the harm principle, the harm test, and legal moralism combined
can justify state interference, the censorship and regulation of pornographic
content will be brought into question. Pornographic content such as videos,
pictures and audio are known to be of conflict between public morality and
individual interest. Porn, in its intended state would be a question of
morality before it’s a question of legality. If both parties in pornographic
content are consensual then physical harm is deemed irrelevant and under the
harm principle pornography cannot be censored. But the aspect of consent is often
based on assumption, this is pointed out by Lori Gruen when she wrote, “Women’s
protests or refusals are not recognized as legitimate” (165), she explains that
even in the act of a woman saying “no”
it’s often portrayed as “sexual-language” (165) and not a denial or retraction
of consent to the participation in sexually explicit activities. Unless consent
is put as a disclaimer before the sexual acts are shown on screen, there is no
way to truly know which parties have or haven’t agreed to all the acts that
will be filmed and produced. But consent is unfortunately a question of morals,
not harm, “moralism cannot override the value of liberty” (Gruen,159). This is
where the theory of legal moralism falls short, the sheer aspect of indecency could
not justify the interference from the state that would allow censorship and
regulation or pornography. And, Mills harm principle would only be applicable
in the case of nonconsensual physical harm caused to women through the
portrayal of male superiority in physical dominance.
Neither filter of harm, the harm principle by John Stuart Mill, legal moralims or the harm test, is applicable or fully sound in every scenario where personal liberty and democratic values are at stake. The harm principle allows you to fully exercise your right to communicate any view or idea you have until you risk harming another, but like a road, there are two sides to a functioning system, in alignment with legality there is morality. Legal moralism advocates for the better interest of society, protecting individuals from “moral disease” (Gruen, 158), but morals aren’t always sound in the eyes of the law. A state can only justifiably intrude on one’s rights to free speech if they risk harm to the values of a democratic society or those able to receive your harmful message. This may be an inconvenience in the spreading of a speaker’s ideas, but it is justifiable in the name of liberty, autonomy and equality.
Work
Cited
Gruen, Lori. ‘Pornography and Censorship’, in R.G. Frey and Christopher Heath Wellman (eds.). A Companion to Applied Ethics. Oxford: Blackwell, 2005, 154-166.Lukianoff, Greg, and Jonathan Haidt. ‘The Coddling of the American Mind’, The Atlantic, September 2015, https://www.theatlantic.com/magazine/archive/2015/09/the-coddlingof-the-american-mind/399356/McGowan, Mary Kate. ‘The Ethics of Free Speech’, in John Skorupski (ed.). The Routledge Companion to Ethics. London: Routledge, 2010, 769-780.Sumner, L.W. ‘Hate Crimes, Literature, and Speech’, in R.G. Frey and Christopher Heath Wellman (eds.). A Companion to Applied Ethics. Oxford: Blackwell, 2005. [142-153]Warburton, Nigel, Free Speech: A Very Short Introduction, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009Himma, Kenneth Einar. “Philosophy of Law.” Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2018, www.iep.utm.edu/law-phil/.
Top-quality papers guaranteed
100% original papers
We sell only unique pieces of writing completed according to your demands.
Confidential service
We use security encryption to keep your personal data protected.
Money-back guarantee
We can give your money back if something goes wrong with your order.
Enjoy the free features we offer to everyone
-
Title page
Get a free title page formatted according to the specifics of your particular style.
-
Custom formatting
Request us to use APA, MLA, Harvard, Chicago, or any other style for your essay.
-
Bibliography page
Don’t pay extra for a list of references that perfectly fits your academic needs.
-
24/7 support assistance
Ask us a question anytime you need to—we don’t charge extra for supporting you!
Calculate how much your essay costs
What we are popular for
- English 101
- History
- Business Studies
- Management
- Literature
- Composition
- Psychology
- Philosophy
- Marketing
- Economics